home *** CD-ROM | disk | FTP | other *** search
- SUPREME COURT OF THE UNITED STATES
- --------
- Nos. 91-155 and 91-339
- --------
- INTERNATIONAL SOCIETY FOR KRISHNA CON-
- SCIOUSNESS, INC., and BRIAN RUMBAUGH,
- PETITIONERS
- 91-155 v.
- WALTER LEE
-
- WALTER LEE, SUPERINTENDENT OF PORT
- AUTHORITY POLICE
- 91-339 v.
- INTERNATIONAL SOCIETY FOR KRISHNA CON-
- SCIOUSNESS, INC., et al.
- on writs of certiorari to the united states court of
- appeals for the second circuit
- [June 26, 1992]
-
- Justice Kennedy, with whom Justice Blackmun,
- Justice Stevens, and Justice Souter join as to Part I,
- concurring in the judgment.
- While I concur in the judgment affirming in this case, my
- analysis differs in substantial respects from that of the
- Court. In my view the airport corridors and shopping areas
- outside of the passenger security zones, areas operated by
- the Port Authority, are public forums, and speech in those
- places is entitled to protection against all government
- regulation inconsistent with public forum principles. The
- Port Authority's blanket prohibition on the distribution or
- sale of literature cannot meet those stringent standards,
- and I agree it is invalid under the First and Fourteenth
- Amendments. The Port Authority's rule disallowing in-
- person solicitation of money for immediate payment,
- however, is in my view a narrow and valid regulation of the
- time, place, and manner of protected speech in this forum,
- or else is a valid regulation of the nonspeech element of
- expressive conduct. I would sustain the Port Authority's
- ban on solicitation and receipt of funds.
- I
- An earlier opinion expressed my concern that -[i]f our
- public forum jurisprudence is to retain vitality, we must
- recognize that certain objective characteristics of Govern-
- ment property and its customary use by the public may
- control- the status of the property. United States v.
- Kokinda, 497 U. S. 720, 737 (1990) (Kennedy, J., concur-
- ring in judgment). The case before us does not heed that
- principle. Our public forum doctrine ought not to be a
- jurisprudence of categories rather than ideas or convert
- what was once an analysis protective of expression into one
- which grants the government authority to restrict speech by
- fiat. I believe that the Court's public forum analysis in this
- case is inconsistent with the values underlying the speech
- and press clauses of the First Amendment.
- Our public forum analysis has its origins in Justice
- Roberts' rather sweeping dictum in Hague v. Committee for
- Industrial Organization, 307 U. S. 496, 515 (1939); see also
- ante, at 6. The doctrine was not stated with much precision
- or elaboration, though, until our more recent decisions in
- Perry Education Assn. v. Perry Local Educators' Assn., 460
- U. S. 37 (1983), and Cornelius v. NAACP Legal Defense &
- Educational Fund, Inc., 473 U. S. 788 (1985). These cases
- describe a three part analysis to designate government-
- owned property as either a traditional public forum, a
- designated public forum, or a nonpublic forum. Perry,
- supra, at 45-46; ante, at 5. The Court today holds that
- traditional public forums are limited to public property
- which have as -`a principal purpose . . . the free exchange
- of ideas'-; ante, at 6 (quoting Cornelius, supra, at 800),
- ante, at 1 (opinion of O'Connor, J.); and that this purpose
- must be evidenced by a long-standing historical practice of
- permitting speech. Ante, at 7; ante, at 1-2 (opinion of
- O'Connor, J.). The Court also holds that designated
- forums consist of property which the government intends to
- open for public discourse. Ante, at 6, citing Cornelius,
- supra, at 802; ante, at 2 (opinion of O'Connor, J.). All
- other types of property are, in the Court's view, nonpublic
- forums (in other words, not public forums), and govern-
- ment-imposed restrictions of speech in these places will be
- upheld so long as reasonable and viewpoint-neutral. Under
- this categorical view the application of public-forum
- analysis to airport terminals seems easy. Airports are of
- course public spaces of recent vintage, and so there can be
- no time-honored tradition associated with airports of
- permitting free speech. Ante, at 7. And because govern-
- ments have often attempted to restrict speech within
- airports, it follows a fortiori under the Court's analysis that
- they cannot be so-called -designated- forums. Ibid. So, the
- Court concludes, airports must be nonpublic forums, subject
- to minimal First Amendment protection.
- This analysis is flawed at its very beginning. It leaves
- the government with almost unlimited authority to restrict
- speech on its property by doing nothing more than articu-
- lating a non-speech-related purpose for the area, and it
- leaves almost no scope for the development of new public
- forums absent the rare approval of the government. The
- Court's error lies in its conclusion that the public-forum
- status of public property depends on the government's
- defined purpose for the property, or on an explicit decision
- by the government to dedicate the property to expressive
- activity. In my view, the inquiry must be an objective one,
- based on the actual, physical characteristics and uses of the
- property. The fact that in our public-forum cases we
- discuss and analyze these precise characteristics tends to
- support my position. Perry, supra, at 46-48; Cornelius,
- supra, at 804-806; Kokinda, supra, at 727-729 (plurality
- opinion).
- The First Amendment is a limitation on government, not
- a grant of power. Its design is to prevent the government
- from controlling speech. Yet under the Court's view the
- authority of the government to control speech on its
- property is paramount, for in almost all cases the critical
- step in the Court's analysis is a classification of the
- property that turns on the government's own definition or
- decision, unconstrained by an independent duty to respect
- the speech its citizens can voice there. The Court acknowl-
- edges as much, by reintroducing today into our First
- Amendment law a strict doctrinal line between the propri-
- etary and regulatory functions of government which I
- thought had been abandoned long ago. Ante, at 4-5;
- compare Davis v. Massachusetts, 167 U. S. 43 (1897); with
- Hague v. Committee for Industrial Organization, supra, at
- 515; Schneider v. State, 308 U. S. 147 (1939); Grayned v.
- City of Rockford, 408 U. S. 104, 115-116 (1972).
- The Court's approach is contrary to the underlying
- purposes of the public forum doctrine. The liberties
- protected by our doctrine derive from the Assembly, as well
- as the Speech and Press Clauses of the First Amendment,
- and are essential to a functioning democracy. See Kalven,
- The Concept of the Public Forum: Cox v. Louisiana, 1965
- S. Ct. Rev. 1, 14, 19. Public places are of necessity the
- locus for discussion of public issues, as well as protest
- against arbitrary government action. At the heart of our
- jurisprudence lies the principle that in a free nation citizens
- must have the right to gather and speak with other persons
- in public places. The recognition that certain government-
- owned property is a public forum provides open notice to
- citizens that their freedoms may be exercised there without
- fear of a censorial government, adding tangible reinforce-
- ment to the idea that we are a free people.
- A fundamental tenet of our Constitution is that the
- government is subject to constraints which private persons
- are not. The public forum doctrine vindicates that principle
- by recognizing limits on the government's control over
- speech activities on property suitable for free expression.
- The doctrine focuses on the physical characteristics of the
- property because government ownership is the source of its
- purported authority to regulate speech. The right of speech
- protected by the doctrine, however, comes not from a
- Supreme Court dictum but from the constitutional recogni-
- tion that the government cannot impose silence on a free
- people.
- The Court's analysis rests on an inaccurate view of
- history. The notion that traditional public forums are
- property which have public discourse as their principal
- purpose is a most doubtful fiction. The types of property
- that we have recognized as the quintessential public forums
- are streets, parks, and sidewalks. Cornelius, 473 U. S., at
- 802; Frisby v. Schultz, 487 U. S. 474, 480-481 (1988). It
- would seem apparent that the principal purpose of streets
- and sidewalks, like airports, is to facilitate transportation,
- not public discourse, and we have recognized as much.
- Schneider v. State, supra, at 160. Similarly, the purpose for
- the creation of public parks may be as much for beauty and
- open space as for discourse. Thus under the Court's
- analysis, even the quintessential public forums would
- appear to lack the necessary elements of what the Court
- defines as a public forum.
- The effect of the Court's narrow view of the first category
- of public forums is compounded by its description of the
- second purported category, the so-called -designated- forum.
- The requirements for such a designation are so stringent
- that I cannot be certain whether the category has any
- content left at all. In any event, it seems evident that
- under the Court's analysis today few if any types of
- property other than those already recognized as public
- forums will be accorded that status.
- The Court's answer to these objections appears to be a
- recourse to history as justifying its recognition of streets,
- parks, and sidewalks, but apparently no other types of
- government property, as traditional public forums. Ante, at
- 7-8. The Court ignores the fact that the purpose of the
- public forum doctrine is to give effect to the broad command
- of the First Amendment to protect speech from governmen-
- tal interference. The jurisprudence is rooted in historic
- practice, but it is not tied to a narrow textual command
- limiting the recognition of new forums. In my view the
- policies underlying the doctrine cannot be given effect
- unless we recognize that open, public spaces and thorough-
- fares which are suitable for discourse may be public forums,
- whatever their historical pedigree and without concern for
- a precise classification of the property. There is support in
- our precedents for such a view. See Lehman v. City of
- Shaker Heights, 418 U. S. 298, 303 (1974) (plurality
- opinion); Hague, 307 U. S., at 515 (speaking of -streets and
- public places- as forums). Without this recognition our
- forum doctrine retains no relevance in times of fast-chang-
- ing technology and increasing insularity. In a country
- where most citizens travel by automobile, and parks all too
- often become locales for crime rather than social inter-
- course, our failure to recognize the possibility that new
- types of government property may be appropriate forums
- for speech will lead to a serious curtailment of our expres-
- sive activity.
- One of the places left in our mobile society that is
- suitable for discourse is a metropolitan airport. It is of
- particular importance to recognize that such spaces are
- public forums because in these days an airport is one of the
- few government-owned spaces where many persons have
- extensive contact with other members of the public. Given
- that private spaces of similar character are not subject to
- the dictates of the First Amendment, see Hudgens v. NLRB,
- 424 U. S. 507 (1976), it is critical that we preserve these
- areas for protected speech. In my view, our public forum
- doctrine must recognize this reality, and allow the creation
- of public forums which do not fit within the narrow tradi-
- tion of streets, sidewalks, and parks. We have allowed
- flexibility in our doctrine to meet changing technologies in
- other areas of constitutional interpretation, see, e.g., Katz
- v. United States, 389 U. S. 347 (1967), and I believe we
- must do the same with the First Amendment.
- I agree with the Court that government property of a type
- which by history and tradition has been available for speech
- activity must continue to be recognized as a public forum.
- Ante, at 7. In my view, however, constitutional protection
- is not confined to these properties alone. Under the proper
- circumstances I would accord public forum status to other
- forms of property, regardless of its ancient or contemporary
- origins and whether or not it fits within a narrow historic
- tradition. If the objective, physical characteristics of the
- property at issue and the actual public access and uses
- which have been permitted by the government indicate that
- expressive activity would be appropriate and compatible
- with those uses, the property is a public forum. The most
- important considerations in this analysis are whether the
- property shares physical similarities with more traditional
- public forums, whether the government has permitted or
- acquiesced in broad public access to the property, and
- whether expressive activity would tend to interfere in a
- significant way with the uses to which the government has
- as a factual matter dedicated the property. In conducting
- the last inquiry, courts must consider the consistency of
- those uses with expressive activities in general, rather than
- the specific sort of speech at issue in the case before it;
- otherwise the analysis would be one not of classification but
- rather of case-by-case balancing, and would provide little
- guidance to the State regarding its discretion to regulate
- speech. Courts must also consider the availability of
- reasonable time, place, and manner restrictions in under-
- taking this compatibility analysis. The possibility of some
- theoretical inconsistency between expressive activities and
- the property's uses should not bar a finding of a public
- forum, if those inconsistencies can be avoided through
- simple and permitted regulations.
- The second category of the Court's jurisprudence, the so-
- called designated forum, provides little, if any, additional
- protection for speech. Where government property does not
- satisfy the criteria of a public forum, the government
- retains the power to dedicate the property for speech,
- whether for all expressive activity or for limited purposes
- only. See ante, at 5; Perry, 460 U. S., at 45-46; Southeast-
- ern Promotions, Ltd. v. Conrad, 420 U. S. 546 (1975). I do
- not quarrel with the fact that speech must often be restrict-
- ed on property of this kind to retain the purpose for which
- it has been designated. And I recognize that when property
- has been designated for a particular expressive use, the
- government may choose to eliminate that designation. But
- this increases the need to protect speech in other places,
- where discourse may occur free of such restrictions. In
- some sense the government always retains authority to
- close a public forum, by selling the property, changing its
- physical character, or changing its principal use. Otherwise
- the State would be prohibited from closing a park, or
- eliminating a street or sidewalk, which no one has under-
- stood the public forum doctrine to require. The difference
- is that when property is a protected public forum the State
- may not by fiat assert broad control over speech or expres-
- sive activities; it must alter the objective physical character
- or uses of the property, and bear the attendant costs, to
- change the property's forum status.
- Under this analysis, it is evident that the public spaces
- of the Port Authority's airports are public forums. First,
- the District Court made detailed findings regarding the
- physical similarities between the Port Authority's airports
- and public streets. 721 F. Supp. 572, 576-577 (SDNY
- 1989). These findings show that the public spaces in the
- airports are broad, public thoroughfares full of people and
- lined with stores and other commercial activities. An
- airport corridor is of course not a street, but that is not the
- proper inquiry. The question is one of physical similarities,
- sufficient to suggest that the airport corridor should be a
- public forum for the same reasons that streets and side-
- walks have been treated as public forums by the people who
- use them.
- Second, the airport areas involved here are open to the
- public without restriction. Ibid. Plaintiffs do not seek
- access to the secured areas of the airports, nor do I suggest
- that these areas would be public forums. And while most
- people who come to the Port Authority's airports do so for
- a reason related to air travel, either because they are
- passengers or because they are picking up or dropping off
- passengers, this does not distinguish an airport from streets
- or sidewalks, which most people use for travel. See supra,
- at ---. Further, the group visiting the airports encom-
- passes a vast portion of the public: In 1986 the Authority's
- three airports served over 78 million passengers. It is the
- very breadth and extent of the public's use of airports that
- makes it imperative to protect speech rights there. Of
- course, airport operators retain authority to restrict public
- access when necessary, for instance to respond to special
- security concerns. But if the Port Authority allows the uses
- and open access to airports that is shown on this record, it
- cannot argue that some vestigial power to change its
- practices bars the conclusion that its airports are public
- forums, any more than the power to bulldoze a park bars a
- finding that a public forum exists so long as the open use
- does.
- Third, and perhaps most important, it is apparent from
- the record, and from the recent history of airports, that
- when adequate time, place, and manner regulations are in
- place, expressive activity is quite compatible with the uses
- of major airports. The Port Authority's primary argument
- to the contrary is that the problem of congestion in its
- airports' corridors makes expressive activity inconsistent
- with the airports' primary purpose, which is to facilitate air
- travel. The First Amendment is often inconvenient. But
- that is besides the point. Inconvenience does not absolve
- the government of its obligation to tolerate speech. The
- Authority makes no showing that any real impediments to
- the smooth functioning of the airports cannot be cured with
- reasonable time, place, and manner regulations. In fact,
- the history of the Authority's own airports, as well as other
- major airports in this country, leaves little doubt that such
- a solution is quite feasible. The Port Authority has for
- many years permitted expressive activities by the plaintiffs
- and others, without any apparent interference with its
- ability to meet its transportation purposes. App. 462,
- 469-470; see also ante, at 8 (opinion of O'Connor, J.). The
- Federal Aviation Authority, in its operation of the airports
- of the Nation's capital, has issued rules which allow
- regulated expressive activity within specified areas, without
- any suggestion that the speech would be incompatible with
- the airports' business. 14 CFR 159.93, 159.94 (1992).
- And in fact expressive activity has been a commonplace
- feature of our Nation's major airports for many years, in
- part because of the wide consensus among the Courts of
- Appeals, prior to the decision in this case, that the public
- spaces of airports are public forums. See, e.g., Chicago
- Area Military Project v. Chicago, 508 F. 2d 921 (CA7), cert.
- denied, 421 U. S. 992 (1975); Fernandes v. Limmer, 663 F.
- 2d 619 (CA5 1981), cert. dism'd, 458 U. S. 1124 (1982);
- United States Southwest Africa/Namibia Trade & Cultural
- Council v. United States, 228 U. S. App. D.C. 191, 708 F. 2d
- 760 (1983); Jews for Jesus, Inc. v. Board of Airport Com-
- m'rs, 785 F. 2d 791 (CA9 1986), aff'd on other grounds, 482
- U. S. 569 (1987); Jamison v. St. Louis, 828 F. 2d 1280 (CA8
- 1987), cert. denied, 485 U. S. 987 (1988). As the District
- Court recognized, the logical consequence of Port Author-
- ity's congestion argument is that the crowded streets and
- sidewalks of major cities cannot be public forums. 721 F.
- Supp., at 578. These problems have been dealt with in the
- past, and in other settings, through proper time, place, and
- manner restrictions; and the Port Authority does not make
- any showing that similar regulations would not be effective
- in its airports. The Port Authority makes a half-hearted
- argument that the special security concerns associated with
- airports suggest they are not public forums; but this
- position is belied by the unlimited public access the
- Authority allows to its airports. This access demonstrates
- that the Port Authority does not consider the general public
- to pose a serious security threat, and there is no evidence
- in the record that persons engaged in expressive activities
- are any different.
- The danger of allowing the government to suppress
- speech is shown in the case now before us. A grant of
- plenary power allows the government to tilt the dialogue
- heard by the public, to exclude many, more marginal voices.
- The first challenged Port Authority regulation establishes
- a flat prohibition on -[t]he sale or distribution of flyers,
- brochures, pamphlets, books or any other printed or written
- material,- if conducted within the airport terminal, -in a
- continuous or repetitive manner.- We have long recognized
- that the right to distribute flyers and literature lies at the
- heart of the liberties guaranteed by the Speech and Press
- Clauses of the First Amendment. See, e.g., Schneider v.
- State, 308 U. S. 147 (1939); Murdock v. Pennsylvania, 319
- U. S. 105 (1943). The Port Authority's rule, which prohibits
- almost all such activity, is among the most restrictive
- possible of those liberties. The regulation is in fact so broad
- and restrictive of speech, Justice O'Connor finds it void
- even under the standards applicable to government regula-
- tions in nonpublic forums. Ante, at 7-8. I have no difficul-
- ty deciding the regulation cannot survive the far more strin-
- gent rules applicable to regulations in public forums. The
- regulation is not drawn in narrow terms and it does not
- leave open ample alternative channels for communication.
- See Ward v. Rock Against Racism, 491 U. S. 781, 791
- (1989). The Port Authority's concerns with the problem of
- congestion can be addressed through narrow restrictions on
- the time and place of expressive activity, see ante, at 8
- (opinion of O'Connor, J.). I would strike down the regula-
- tion as an unconstitutional restriction of speech.
- II
- It is my view, however, that the Port Authority's ban on
- the -solicitation and receipt of funds- within its airport
- terminals should be upheld under the standards applicable
- to speech regulations in public forums. The regulation may
- be upheld as either a reasonable time, place, and manner
- restriction, or as a regulation directed at the nonspeech
- element of expressive conduct. The two standards have
- considerable overlap in a case like this one.
- It is well settled that -even in a public forum the govern-
- ment may impose reasonable restrictions on the time, place,
- or manner of protected speech, provided the restrictions `are
- justified without reference to the content of the regulated
- speech, that they are narrowly tailored to serve a signifi-
- cant governmental interest, and that they leave open ample
- alternative channels for communication of the information.'-
- Ward, supra, at 791 (quoting Clark v. Community for
- Creative Non-Violence, 468 U. S. 288, 293 (1984)). We have
- held further that the government in appropriate circum-
- stances may regulate conduct, even if the conduct has an
- expressive component. United States v. O'Brien, 391 U. S.
- 367 (1968). And in several recent cases we have recognized
- that the standards for assessing time, place, and manner
- restrictions are little, if any, different from the standards
- applicable to regulations of conduct with an expressive
- component. Clark, supra, at 298, and n. 8; Ward, supra, at
- 798; Barnes v. Glen Theatre, Inc., 501 U. S. ---, --- (1991)
- (slip op., at 5) (plurality opinion); see generally Kalven,
- 1965 S. Ct. Rev., at 23, 27 (arguing that all speech contains
- elements of conduct which may be regulated). The conflu-
- ence of the two tests is well demonstrated by a case like
- this, where the government regulation at issue can be
- described with equal accuracy as a regulation of the manner
- of expression, or as a regulation of conduct with an expres-
- sive component.
- I am in full agreement with the statement of the Court
- that solicitation is a form of protected speech. Ante, at 4;
- see also Riley v. National Federation of Blind, 487 U. S.
- 781, 788-789 (1988); Schaumburg v. Citizens for a Better
- Environment, 444 U. S. 620, 629 (1980); Murdock v.
- Pennsylvania, supra. If the Port Authority's solicitation
- regulation prohibited all speech which requested the
- contribution of funds, I would conclude that it was a direct,
- content-based restriction of speech in clear violation of the
- First Amendment. The Authority's regulation does not
- prohibit all solicitation, however; it prohibits the -solicita-
- tion and receipt of funds.- I do not understand this
- regulation to prohibit all speech that solicits funds. It
- reaches only personal solicitations for immediate payment
- of money. Otherwise, the -receipt of funds- phrase would
- be written out of the provision. The regulation does not
- cover, for example, the distribution of preaddressed enve-
- lopes along with a plea to contribute money to the distribu-
- tor or his organization. As I understand the restriction it
- is directed only at the physical exchange of money, which is
- an element of conduct interwoven with otherwise expressive
- solicitation. In other words, the regulation permits expres-
- sion that solicits funds, but limits the manner of that
- expression to forms other than the immediate receipt of
- money.
- So viewed, I believe the Port Authority's rule survives our
- test for speech restrictions in the public forum. In-person
- solicitation of funds, when combined with immediate receipt
- of that money, creates a risk of fraud and duress which is
- well recognized, and which is different in kind from other
- forms of expression or conduct. Travelers who are unfamil-
- iar with the airport, perhaps even unfamiliar with this
- country, its customs and its language, are an easy prey for
- the money solicitor. I agree in full with the Court's
- discussion of these dangers in No. 91-155. Ante, at 10-11;
- ante, at 5 (opinion of O'Connor, J.). I would add that our
- precedents as well as the actions of coordinate branches of
- government support this conclusion. We have in the past
- recognized that in-person solicitation has been associated
- with coercive or fraudulent conduct. Cantwell v. Connecti-
- cut, 310 U. S. 296, 306 (1940); Riley, supra, at 800; Heffron
- v. International Society for Krishna Consciousness, Inc., 452
- U. S. 640, 657 (1981) (Brennan, J., concurring in part and
- dissenting in part); Schaumburg, supra, at 636-638. In
- addition, the federal government has adopted regulations
- which acknowledge and respond to the serious problems
- associated with solicitation. The National Park Service has
- enacted a flat ban on the direct solicitation of money in the
- parks of the Nation's capital within its control. 36 CFR
- 7.96(h) (1991); see also United States v. Kokinda, 497
- U. S., at 739 (Kennedy, J., concurring in judgment). Also,
- the Federal Aviation Authority, in its administration of the
- airports of Washington, D.C., even while permitting the
- solicitation of funds has adopted special rules to prevent
- coercive, harassing, or repetitious behavior. 14 CFR
- 159.94(e) - (h) (1992). And in the commercial sphere, the
- Federal Trade Commission has long held that -it constitutes
- an unfair and deceptive act or practice- to make a door-to-
- door sale without allowing the buyer a three-day -cooling-off
- period- during which time he or she may cancel the sale.
- 16 CFR 429.1 (1992). All of these measures are based on
- a recognition that requests for immediate payment of
- money create a strong potential for fraud or undue pres-
- sure, in part because of the lack of time for reflection. As
- the Court recounts, questionable practices associated with
- solicitation can include the targeting of vulnerable and
- easily coerced persons, misrepresentation of the solicitor's
- cause, and outright theft. Ante, at 10-11; see also Interna-
- tional Society for Krishna Consciousness, Inc. v. Barber, 506
- F. Supp. 147, 159-163 (NDNY 1980), rev'd on other
- grounds, 650 F. 2d 430 (CA2 1981).
- Because the Port Authority's solicitation ban is directed
- at these abusive practices and not at any particular
- message, idea, or form of speech, the regulation is a
- content-neutral rule serving a significant government
- interest. We have held that the content neutrality of a rule
- must be assessed based on whether it is -`justified without
- reference to the content of the regulated speech.'- Ward,
- 491 U. S., at 791 (quoting Clark, 468 U. S., at 293) (empha-
- sis in original). It is apparent that the justification for the
- solicitation ban is unrelated to the content of speech or the
- identity of the speaker. There can also be no doubt that the
- prevention of fraud and duress is a significant government
- interest. The government cannot, of course, prohibit speech
- for the sole reason that it is concerned the speech may be
- fraudulent. Schaumburg, 444 U. S., at 637. But the Port
- Authority's regulation does not do this. It recognizes that
- the risk of fraud and duress is intensified by particular
- conduct, the immediate exchange of money; and it address-
- es only that conduct. We have recognized that such
- narrowly drawn regulations are in fact the proper means
- for addressing the dangers which can be associated with
- speech. Ibid.; Riley, 487 U. S., at 799, n. 11.
- To survive scrutiny, the regulation must be drawn in
- narrow terms to accomplish its end and leave open ample
- alternative channels for communication. Regarding the
- former requirement, we have held that to be narrowly
- tailored a regulation need not be the least restrictive or
- least intrusive means of achieving an end. The regulation
- must be reasonable, and must not burden substantially
- more speech than necessary. Ward, supra, at 798-800.
- Under this standard the solicitation ban survives with ease,
- because it prohibits only solicitation of money for immediate
- receipt. The regulation does not burden any broader
- category of speech or expressive conduct than is the source
- of the evil sought to be avoided. And in fact, the regulation
- is even more narrow because it only prohibits such behavior
- if conducted in a continuous or repetitive manner. The Port
- Authority has made a reasonable judgment that this type
- of conduct raises the most serious concerns, and it is
- entitled to deference. My conclusion is not altered by the
- fact that other means, for example the regulations adopted
- by the Federal Aviation Authority to govern its airports,
- may be available to address the problems associated with
- solicitation, because the existence of less intrusive means is
- not decisive. Our cases do not so limit the government's
- regulatory flexibility. See Ward, supra, at 800.
- I have little difficulty in deciding that the Port Authority
- has left open ample alternative channels for the communi-
- cation of the message which is an aspect of solicitation. As
- already discussed, see supra, at --- the Authority's rule
- does not prohibit all solicitation of funds: It restricts only
- the manner of the solicitation, or the conduct associated
- with solicitation, to prohibit immediate receipt of the
- solicited money. Requests for money continue to be
- permitted, and in the course of requesting money solicitors
- may explain their cause, or the purposes of their organiza-
- tion, without violating the regulation. It is only if the
- solicitor accepts immediate payment that a violation occurs.
- Thus the solicitor can continue to disseminate his message,
- for example by distributing preaddressed envelopes in
- which potential contributors may mail their donations. See
- supra, at ---.
- Much of what I have said about the solicitation of funds
- may seem to apply to the sale of literature, but the differ-
- ences between the two activities are of sufficient signifi-
- cance to require they be distinguished for constitutional
- purposes. The Port Authority's flat ban on the distribution
- or sale of printed material must, in my view, fall in its
- entirety. See supra, at ---. The application of our time,
- place, and manner test to the ban on sales leads to a result
- quite different from the solicitation ban. For one, the
- government interest in regulating the sales of literature is
- not as powerful as in the case of solicitation. The danger of
- a fraud arising from such sales is much more limited than
- from pure solicitation, because in the case of a sale the
- nature of the exchange tends to be clearer to both parties.
- Also, the Port Authority's sale regulation is not as narrowly
- drawn as the solicitation rule, since it does not specify the
- receipt of money as a critical element of a violation. And
- perhaps most important, the flat ban on sales of literature
- leaves open fewer alternative channels of communication
- than the Port Authority's more limited prohibition on the
- solicitation and receipt of funds. Given the practicalities
- and ad hoc nature of much expressive activity in the public
- forum, sales of literature must be completed in one transac-
- tion to be workable. Attempting to collect money at another
- time or place is a far less plausible option in the context of
- a sale than when soliciting donations, because the literature
- sought to be sold will under normal circumstances be
- distributed within the forum. These distinctions have been
- recognized by the National Park Service, which permits the
- sale or distribution of literature, while prohibiting solicita-
- tion. Supra, at ---; 36 CFR 7.96(j)(2) (1991). Thus the
- Port Authority's regulation allows no practical means for
- advocates and organizations to sell literature within the
- public forums which are its airports.
- Against all of this must be balanced the great need,
- recognized by our precedents, to give the sale of literature
- full First Amendment protection. We have long recognized
- that to prohibit distribution of literature for the mere
- reason that it is sold would leave organizations seeking to
- spread their message without funds to operate. -It should
- be remembered that the pamphlets of Thomas Paine were
- not distributed free of charge.- Murdock, 319 U. S., at 111;
- see also Schaumburg, supra, at 628-635 (discussing cases).
- The effect of a rule of law distinguishing between sales and
- distribution would be to close the marketplace of ideas to
- less affluent organizations and speakers, leaving speech as
- the preserve of those who are able to fund themselves. One
- of the primary purposes of the public forum is to provide
- persons who lack access to more sophisticated media the
- opportunity to speak. A prohibition on sales forecloses that
- opportunity for the very persons who need it most. And
- while the same arguments might be made regarding
- solicitation of funds, the answer is that the Port Authority
- has not prohibited all solicitation, but only a narrow class
- of conduct associated with a particular manner of solicita-
- tion.
- For these reasons I agree that the Court of Appeals
- should be affirmed in full in finding the Port Authority's
- ban on the distribution or sale of literature unconstitu-
- tional, but upholding the prohibition on solicitation and
- immediate receipt of funds.
-